Evidence for God

A lot of atheist arguments focus on the lack of evidence supporting the truth of various religious beliefs. Famous atheist Christopher Hitchens (God rest his soul) is said to have remarked, That which can be asserted without evidence, can be dismissed without evidence. This is a compelling point, but it has important limitations, both logical and practical.

It’s not a bad argument, of course. “Prove it!” is the ultimate objection in lots of situations, from poker to physics. But in some areas of life, it sounds silly. Suppose you said to me, “I’m glad I became a writer instead of a scientist, because I just don’t have what it takes to be a scientist.” If I jumped up and said, “Prove it!” you wouldn’t know quite how to respond. Or suppose you told me, “Most people lose their faith because, when they are children, religion is shoved down their throats.” By saying “Prove it!” I wouldn’t be either refuting your statement or offering you a meaningful opportunity to justify it. Many things in life, even very important things, aren’t susceptible to rigorous proof.

Atheists reject religion for this reason. As I understand it, the lack-of-evidence argument against religion goes something like this:

Assertions about the Universe are true if and only if they are supported by a particular kind of evidence, namely, evidence that can be tested by third parties in standard ways employing the scientific method.

The logical limitations of this argument can be illustrated by focusing on the evidentiary criteria. The argument does not simply require that assertions be supported by “evidence,” but by experimental evidence, the kind of evidence that a scientist relies on when proving or disproving a hypothesis. When that demand is leveled at the religious person, he or she may well respond, “Of course we don’t have the kind of evidence you’re looking for. That’s why it’s called ‘faith,’ dummy!” And this is where the conversation breaks down and people start yelling at each other.

But get ready for a shocker: From the logical point of view, the religious people have the stronger position. The lack-of-evidence argument relies on an a priori exclusion of the particular type of evidence that most strongly supports religious belief, namely, the testimony of witnesses. Religious beliefs are widely supported by evidence of this sort, and the lack-of-evidence argument provides no justification for excluding it. No one would ask us to rely on the patterns in tea leaves, or kinks in goat entrails, as evidence of earthly events. These forms of evidence are inherently unreliable. But there’s nothing inherently unreliable about testimony. That’s why we use it so extensively in courtrooms. By tinkering with the proof requirements, the atheist creates conditions making it impossible for religious people to justify their beliefs. What really hurts is that the atheist then criticizes them for failing to provide a satisfactory justification.

In the context of religion, the testimony of witnesses shouldn’t be rejected out of hand. Christianity, for example, is internally consistent in this regard, because the founder of Christianity insisted we should consider this very type of evidence. Jesus repeatedly exhorts doubters to be persuaded by testimony, e.g. Luke 7:18-23, John 3:10-11, and his followers make the same argument, e.g. 1 Corinthians 15:3-7. And since Jesus lived in an age before video and laboratory instrumentation, the only evidence that survives is the testimony. So the lack-of-evidence argument excludes all the evidence that Christians have.

The real point of Hitchens’ remark is to assert that religion is unsupported by evidence. This assertion is false, and its falsity is (as a philosopher would say) noncontroversial. Religious beliefs are supported by plenty of evidence. Atheists just exclude the evidence from consideration. And they refuse to justify this exclusion. It is an a priori determination, one that does not depend on experience or evidence.

These a priori justifications for atheism crop up all the time. I recently read an atheist’s rebuttal of near-death experiences, where the person experiences a divine presence. The atheist explained the phenomenon thus: It’s basically the synapses of the brain misfiring due to catastrophic trauma to the brain or the debilitating effects of illness. Well, certainly the experience involved synaptic activity in the brain; all consciousness does. But why insist that, in this instance, the synapses were misfiring? After all, lots of terribly injured and ill people continue to accurately perceive what’s going on around them. The atheist believes that this poor chap’s synapses were misfiring, not because of the report of some device that was monitoring brain activity, but because of the appearance of something in which the atheist does not believe: a divine presence.

Similarly, in Fatima, Portugal, in 1917, tens of thousands of people witnessed apparently miraculous events, including a dramatic change in the appearance of the sun, which shined in different colors and then appeared to oscillate and rapidly approach them. The atheist discounts the testimony of these witnesses, offering the explanation that prolonged staring at the sun, coupled with psychological factors, account for the vision. The atheist prefers this explanation, not because of laboratory experiments in which people stared at the sun and reported the same effect, but because the atheist disallows the possibility that any supernatural factors were at work. If the same crowd had witnessed something the atheist does believe in, like a meteor or an archbishop, then their testimony would be evaluated under a different set of rules. Since they saw a miracle, they are credulous peasants who don’t understand the neurology of vision.

The pattern is the same: If someone provides evidence of a supernatural event, the atheist rejects the evidence, because supernatural events are against the atheist’s belief system.

All this tedious logic doesn’t prove that atheists are wrong and religious people are right. But it shows that atheists, like religious people, take some things on faith. Which is not such a bad thing, really.

If you want to delve into this aspect of atheism, I recommend G.K. Chesterton’s entertaining book Orthodoxy, which is continually in print, and which is available for free online at http://www.ccel.org/ccel/chesterton/orthodoxy.html

Advertisements

3 comments on “Evidence for God

  1. […] The person making this argument has inserted a new premise, which I address elsewhere (see “Evidence for God,” Dec. 18, […]

  2. Rob Tisinai says:

    This is not the lack-of-evidence argument: “Assertions about the Universe are true if and only if they are supported by a particular kind of evidence, namely, evidence that can be tested by third parties in standard ways employing the scientific method.”

    Rather, it’s: “Assertions about the Universe NEED ONLY BE ACCEPTED AS true if they are supported by objective evidence..”

    There’s quite a difference between: “This statement is not true” and “I have no compelling reason to accept this statement as true.” The former is your characterization, but the latter is what the argument is really about. No one I know says that assertions are not true until we have evidence to support them — merely that the assertions (which may be true) have not been demonstrated to be true.

    Also, this statement: “In the context of religion, the testimony of witnesses shouldn’t be rejected out of hand,” seems to be arguing against a straw man. I don’t see this testimony being rejected out of hand. Rather I see a great deal of investigation into when the evidence was recorded, by whom, how it was preserved and transmitted, etc.

    • Your distinction does make a difference, but I don’t think it applies to what Hitchens is saying and what I say he is saying. Yes, taken literally, the Hitchens assertion leaves the listener with the OPTION of dismissing religion. But when did Hitchens ever do that, really? He scorned and ridiculed believers, called them dangerous people. Taken in context, his real argument is:
      What is asserted without evidence must be dismissed.
      Religion is asserted without evidence
      Therefore, religion must be dismissed.

      My quarrel is with the minor premise, and my point is that it contains an embedded argument:
      What is asserted without a certain kind of evidence must be dismissed
      Religion is asserted without a certain kind of evidence
      Therefore, religion must be dismissed.

      I can say with all cheerfulness that, if you don’t know anyone who denies the truth of assertions made without evidence, especially religious assertions, then all I can say is, you’re hanging around with a better class of atheists than I am!

      On the investigation of witness testimony regarding miracles: I’d actually like to know more about that. The only people who investigate miracles in depth, as far as I know, are religious people, only some of whom are trained investigators. I’d like to know what the non-religious people are saying about miracles. There are an awful lot of them around (miracles, I mean), and I wish they got more mainstream attention.

      Peace

Leave a Comment

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out / Change )

Twitter picture

You are commenting using your Twitter account. Log Out / Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out / Change )

Google+ photo

You are commenting using your Google+ account. Log Out / Change )

Connecting to %s